A blog for big questions of philosophy, excerpts from favorite essays, book reviews...
12 Kasım 2014 Çarşamba
Creative Benefits of Keeping a Diary
About the benefits of keeping a diary for those who write...
Keeping a Diary
13 Ekim 2014 Pazartesi
Platonic Paradigm and Parallel Universes
Revisiting Plato's Theory of Forms and "One Over Many" doctrine from a physicist's perspective...
What is there are parallell universes? What if Plato is right?
Parallel Universes
What is there are parallell universes? What if Plato is right?
Parallel Universes
19 Eylül 2014 Cuma
Is there a satisfactory alternative to epistemological skepticism?
Skeptical
arguments challenge even the very solid pieces of our knowledge. Take, for
example, your belief that you have hands. You see your hands, you hold and move
things with them. So, what can possibly threaten your knowledge or true belief
that you have hands?
In this
essay, I shall argue three responses to skepticism based on the brain-in-a-vat
(BIV) hypothesis and conclude that despite their validity and plausibility,
they fall behind skepticism to constitute as satisfactory alternatives.
The skeptical argument can be
constructed as follows[1]:
(1)
I
don’t know that I’m not a BIV.
(2)
If
I don’t know that I’m not a BIV, then I don’t know that I have hands.
(3)
I
don’t know that I have hands.
This argument is indeed a valid argument in the sense that (1) and
(2) are plausible premises and (3) logically
follows from these premises. Regardless of how farfetched or against
commonsense may it seem to assume that you are a brain-in-a-vat, you still
don’t know you are not one. And this very fact is what underlies the strength
of skeptic’s argument: It is straightforward and its premises are difficult to
rule out or there is a possibility that they are true or at the very least we
don’t know that they are false. Hence, any argument developed against
skepticism must question the soundness of
the argument.
In response to BIV argument, G. E. Moore states that
the conclusion of BIV argument is less plausible than its premises and thus reconstructs
the BIV argument (counter-BIV argument) by asserting the opposite of the
skeptic’s conclusion[2]:
(1)
I know that I have hands.
(2)
If
I don’t know that I’m not a BIV, then I don’t know that I have hands.
(3)
I know that I’m not a BIV.
What Moore suggests is that in the face of two
conflicting premises, we should opt for the common-sense premise that we know we have hands, which entails the
conclusion that we know we are not
BIVs.
Though Moorean argument is valid, it is still not a
satisfactory alternative to skepticism. First, it does not explain how Moore knows that he has hands. The skeptic who
asserts that he doesn’t know whether there is an external world might easily
claim that he does not know that he
has hands. He might as well be dreaming that he has hands. Second, the premises
of Moorean argument remain insufficient in convincing the skeptic who would not
agree with its conclusion. And finally, the skeptic might allege that Moorean
premises lack proof in order to constitute as ‘knowledge’.
Another response to skepticism is argued by “Relevant Alternatives” theory, which
basically says that “the main ingredient that must be added to true belief to
make knowledge is that one be in a position to rule out all the relevant alternatives to what one believes”
(DeRose, 1999, p. 14). What underlies the BIV argument is that since we cannot
discriminate between our actually having hands and not being a BIV, we don’t
know that we have hands. According to the relevant alternative theorist, this
discrimination is not relevant anymore because our being a BIV is not a relevant alternative to our having hands.
Thus, we can deduce that we know we have hands.
Accordingly,
the BIV argument can be constructed as follows[3]:
(1)
You know you have hands.
(2)
You know that your having hands
entails your not being a BIV.
(3)
You don’t know that you are not a
BIV.
This argument rejects the second premise of BIV
argument and asserts that you know you have hands though you don’t know you are
not a BIV. This, in turn, implies that this theory denies the “Closure Principle”,
which basically says that if S knows p,
and p entails q; then S knows q. Hence, the main concern that can be raised
by a skeptic against relevant alternatives theory is its denial of this intuitively
appealing principle. Another important problem for this approach is the lack of
a principled basis for what constitutes relevant and irrelevant alternatives.
The contextualist response to BIV argument deploys a
different approach and focuses on the use of the word “know” in differing contexts. The utterance of “I know” can be ascribed freely to knowledge in low-standard
settings, but cannot be done so liberally in high-standard settings. One can
ask what the point is epistemologically in distinguishing between high and
low-standard settings? The point is that the skeptical argument creates such a
context that we count no more as “knowers” even when we utter such a
straightforward sentence as “I know I
have hands”. The skeptic’s demanding high standards raise questions such as
“how do I know my having hands?”, “How do I know that I’m not a BIV who has the
same sensory experiences as a human-being?” On the other hand, in a
non-philosophical sense, I ordinarily do
know that I have hands and cannot be deemed false in claiming so. Since contextualism
employs two types of contexts, it resolves this seemingly paradox and truth-condition holds in both settings.
Thus, contextualism is a plausible argument and preserves
the “Closure Principle”, which holds in both high and low-standard settings:
a.
If the meaning of “know” is set by low
standards, I know that I have hands
and I know that I’m not a BIV.
b. If the meaning of “know” is set by high
standards, I don’t know that I have
hands and I don’t know that I’m not a
BIV.
The main criticism against contextualism is that since
high-standard settings allow the use of skeptic’s argument asserting “I don’t know”, it makes considerable
concessions to skepticism. Another objection is that people are not strictly
context-sensitive, which implies that the way they use the word “know” is not determined at all times. Besides, the way contextualism assumes
strict context-sensitivity ignores people’s intention
when they utter the word “know”.
In summary, skeptical argument seems to enjoy a higher
degree of plausibility and soundness in comparison to responses raised against
it. The strength of the argument mainly stems from the fact that the skeptical
hypothesis is such that “…we cannot rule
out her hypothesis, that it’s possible that her hypothesis is true, or that we
don’t know that her hypothesis is false.” (DeRose, 1999, p. 2)
BIBLIOGRAPHY
DeRose,
Keith (1999), ‘Responding to Skepticism’, Oxford
University Press.
Steap,
Matthias (2005), ‘Epistemology’, The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology/,
accessed June 30, 2014.
Speaks,
Jeff (2004), ‘Moore’s Response to Skepticism’, http://www3.nd.edu/~jspeaks/courses/mcgill/370/Moore-skepticism.pdf,
accessed June 30, 2014.
DeRose,
Keith (1999), ‘Contextualism: An Explanation and Defense’, http://fitelson.org/epistemology/derose.pdf,
accessed July 4, 2014.
[1]
Steap,
Matthias (2005), ‘Epistemology’, The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology/, accessed June 25,
2014
[2]
Steap,
Matthias (2005), ‘Epistemology’, The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology/, accessed June 25,
2014
27 Ağustos 2014 Çarşamba
Socratic Irony and Neuroscience
Socratic Irony and Neuroscience
"The philosopher Socrates lived from 469 to 399 B.C. Although he is one of history’s most famous philosophers—arguably the most famous—he never wrote a word, unless we count a poem that he wrote in prison in Athens while awaiting execution. Why, you ask, was someone so important put to death? We know a great deal about the events leading up to his execution, mainly from an amazing document that survives, called the Apology. It was written by Plato and purports to be a recounting of what Socrates said in his defense at his trial. But, trial for what you ask, what was he charged with? The official charge was impiety, which to the Athenians at that time meant roughly that he was not a good citizen. That charge consisted of three counts: First, Socrates was charged with not worshipping the gods of Athens, second, he was charged with creating new gods, and third, he was charged with corrupting the youth. The last charge came about because many young men would follow Socrates around as he questioned the leading citizens of Athens, or anyone who claimed to have knowledge. The records of these interactions are part of what are known as the platonic dialogues, marvelous works of literature produced by his student Plato that depict what Socratic questioning was like. In them, Socrates shows via questioning that the person he is talking with who is claiming to have knowledge really doesn’t possess it, since he contradicts himself, or is simply unable to answer Socrates’ questions adequately..."
Follow the link below to read the rest of the article...
Socratic Irony and Neuroscience
13 Ağustos 2014 Çarşamba
Excerpt from The Phantoms in the Brain
“…Consider next the simple act of smiling,
something we all do every day in social situations. You see a good friend and
you grin. But what happens when that friend aims a camera at your face and asks
you to smile on command? Instead of a natural expression, you produce a hideous
grimace. Paradoxically, an act that you perform effortlessly dozens of times
each day becomes extraordinarily difficult to perform when someone simply asks
you to do it. You might think it’s because if you walk over to any mirror and
try smiling, I assure you that the same grimace will appear.
The reason these two kinds of smiles differ is
that different brain regions handle them, and only one of them contains a
specialized “smile circuit.” A spontaneous smile is produced by the basal
ganglia, clusters of cells found between the brain’s higher cortex (where
thinking and planning take place) and the evolutionary older thalamus. When you
encounter a friendly face, the visual message from that face eventually reaches
the brain’s emotional center or limbic system and is subsequently relayed to
the basal ganglia, which orchestrate the sequences of facial muscle activity
needed for producing a natural smile. When this circuit is activated, your
smile is genuine. The entire cascade of events, once set in motion, happens in
a fraction of a second without the thinking parts of your cortex ever being
involved…”
Phantoms in the Brain, p. 13
23 Haziran 2014 Pazartesi
This is your brain on writing
"........
The researchers, led by Martin Lotze of the University of Greifswald in Germany, observed a broad network of regions in the brain working together as people produced their stories. But there were notable differences between the two groups of subjects. The inner workings of the professionally trained writers in the bunch, the scientists argue, showed some similarities to people who are skilled at other complex actions, like music or sports....."
Follow the link for the rest of the article:
Your brain on writing
The researchers, led by Martin Lotze of the University of Greifswald in Germany, observed a broad network of regions in the brain working together as people produced their stories. But there were notable differences between the two groups of subjects. The inner workings of the professionally trained writers in the bunch, the scientists argue, showed some similarities to people who are skilled at other complex actions, like music or sports....."
Follow the link for the rest of the article:
Your brain on writing
27 Mayıs 2014 Salı
Freedom and resentment
“Freedom and resentment” is one critical essay of Strawson,
which was originally delivered as a lecture to the British Academy and then
published in Proceedings of the British
Academy (1962).
Here he is...
In his paper, overall, Strawson argues the role and implications of determinism (assuming the possible truth of determinism) for agents susceptible of moral assessment. His main argument is that "pessimism" and "optimism" about the compatibility of determinism and morality needn't be mutually exclusive, that is to say, they can somehow be reconciled.
But how come? His argument about the compatibility of determinism and morality is further strengthened by his differentiation of attitudes as:
1. Reactive attitudes (such as resentment and gratitude)
2. Moral reactive attitudes
3. Self reactive attitudes
The key question in his essay is that if we assume determinism to hold true, would we have to assess everybody with an "objective attitude"?
According to Strawson "No!" because first of all, being a human renders reactive attitudes natural even under the case in which the agents are deemed to be free from responsibility (answerability, accountability) due to various reasons.
Likewise, in arguing moral attitudes, Strawson claims that believing determinism to be true does not necessarily lead us to "abandon moral dispprobation of agents."
In summary, he arrives at the general conclusion that the reasons of the fact that in some circumstances we need to suspend our moral reactive attitudes toward some agent doesn't entail the truth of determinism. Furthermore, rationality is not disputable for issues related to the very nature of human being such as having reactive attitudes.
12 Mayıs 2014 Pazartesi
What are you?
In his second meditation, after seeking the truth that
leaves no room for doubt, Descartes finally becomes sure about something: “He is, he exists.”
The famous quote of him does not come yet in its complete
form. But he basically says “I am, I
exist’, is necessarily true whenever it is put forward by me or conceived
in my mind.” He is pretty close though…
Even the existence of a malicious demon who tries to deceive
him all the time cannot deceive him about the very fact that he thinks. As long
as he is busy thinking about whether he is imagining in his sleep or not,
whether his senses sometimes deceive him or not he exists.
But what entails this “thinking”? What does he mean by
thinking, the endeavour of his soul?
The attributes, according to Descartes that make him a
thinking thing are doubting,
understanding, affirming, denying, being willing or unwilling, imagining and
having sensory perceptions.
What do you think? Do you think this list is fair enough? If
not, what are some of the attributes you assign to thinking?
1 Mayıs 2014 Perşembe
What the bleep do we know?
Long time ago, I had watched the movie named "What the bleep do we know?"
It was actually a documentary type movie about how the quantum physics changed the way we perceive and interpret the seemingly real world we live in.
Now as I am reading Descartes' meditations, I cannot avoid, but think that modern philosophers do not apreciate as much Descartes' starting point by questioning the existence of anything as they should in the light of quantum theory's recent findings.
Anyway, as Simon Blackburn says:
It was actually a documentary type movie about how the quantum physics changed the way we perceive and interpret the seemingly real world we live in.
Now as I am reading Descartes' meditations, I cannot avoid, but think that modern philosophers do not apreciate as much Descartes' starting point by questioning the existence of anything as they should in the light of quantum theory's recent findings.
Anyway, as Simon Blackburn says:
"Perhaps the most unsettling thought many of us have, often quite early on in childhood, is that the whole world might be a dream; that the ordinary scenes and objects of everyday life might be fantasies. The reality we live in may be a virtual reality, spun out of our own minds, or perhaps injected into our minds by some sinister Other. Of course, such thought come, and then go. Most of us shake them off. But why are we right to do so? How can we know that the world as we take it to be, is the world as it is? How do we begin to think about the relation between appearance and reality: things as we take them to be, as opposed to things as they are?" (Think, pp. 15, Simon Blackburn)
28 Nisan 2014 Pazartesi
The Value of Philosophy
"......But further, if we are not to fail in our endeavour to determine the value of philosophy, we must first free our minds from the prejudices of what are wrongly called 'practical' men. The 'practical' man, as this word is often used, is one who recognizes only material needs, who realizes that men must have food for the body, but is oblivious of the necessity of providing food for the mind. If all men were well off, if poverty and disease had been reduced to their lowest possible point, there would still remain much to be done to produce a valuable society; and even in the existing world the goods of the mind are at least as important as the goods of the body. It is exclusively among the goods of the mind that the value of philosophy is to be found; and only those who are not indifferent to these goods can be persuaded that the study of philosophy is not a waste of time.
....
The value of philosophy is, in fact, to be sought largely in its very uncertainty. The man who has no tincture of philosophy goes through life imprisoned in the prejudices derived from common sense, from the habitual beliefs of his age or his nation, and from convictions which have grown up in his mind without the co-operation or consent of his deliberate reason. To such a man the world tends to become definite, finite, obvious; common objects rouse no questions, and unfamiliar possibilities are contemptuously rejected. As soon as we begin to philosophize, on the contrary, we find, as we saw in our opening chapters, that even the most everyday things lead to problems to which only very incomplete answers can be given. Philosophy, though unable to tell us with certainty what is the true answer to the doubts which it raises, is able to suggest many possibilities which enlarge our thoughts and free them from the tyranny of custom. Thus, while diminishing our feeling of certainty as to what things are, it greatly increases our knowledge as to what they may be; it removes the somewhat arrogant dogmatism of those who have never travelled into the region of liberating doubt, and it keeps alive our sense of wonder by showing familiar things in an unfamiliar aspect...."
From Bertrand Russell's The Problems of Philosophy
Kaydol:
Kayıtlar (Atom)